Counterexample: a pair of linearly ordered sets that are isomorphic to subsets of the other, but not...
$begingroup$
I have encountered myself with the following exercise:
Let $langle A, <_Rrangle$ and $langle B, <_Srangle$ be two linearly ordered sets so that each one is isomorphic to a subset of the other, that is, there exists $A'subseteq A$ and $B'subseteq B$ such that:
$$langle A,<_Rrangleconglangle B',<_Scap(B'times B')rangleqquad&qquadlangle B,<_Srangleconglangle A',<_Rcap(A'times A')rangle$$
Is it necessarily true that $langle A,<_Rrangleconglangle B,<_Srangle$?
The original statement talked about well-ordered sets, but that case is pretty easy, because supposing that $langle B',<_Scap(B'times B')rangle$ is not isomorphic to $langle B,<_Srangle$, the theorem of comparison between well-ordered sets assures that $B'$ with its restricted relation $<_S$ is isomorphic to an initial section of $langle B,<_Srangle$. But then, composing the unique isomorphism between $A$ and $B'$ with the restriction to $B'$ of the only isomorphism between $B$ and $A'$, we find that $A$ is isomorphic to a subset of $A$ with strict upper bounds (namely, the image of the element of $B$ that defines the initial section of $B'$ via the isomorphism between $B$ and $A'$) in the sense of $<_R$, which is absurd.
However, when the sets are not well-ordered, can we find a couple of linearly ordered sets that, although verifying the stated property, are not isomorphic to each other?
I have tried with many examples between subsets of $mathbb{R}$ and other subsets of $mathbb{R}$, but it seems that they are all isomorphic to each other.
I ran out of ideas. Are there any counterexamples to this statement? Or does this property actually characterize when two ordered structures are isomorphic? In case the second part holds, why is that the case?
Thanks in advance for your time.
P.S.: I have thought, for instance, that a closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ shouldn't be isomorphic to the whole $mathbb{R}$. How can we prove this assertion, if true?
elementary-set-theory examples-counterexamples order-theory
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I have encountered myself with the following exercise:
Let $langle A, <_Rrangle$ and $langle B, <_Srangle$ be two linearly ordered sets so that each one is isomorphic to a subset of the other, that is, there exists $A'subseteq A$ and $B'subseteq B$ such that:
$$langle A,<_Rrangleconglangle B',<_Scap(B'times B')rangleqquad&qquadlangle B,<_Srangleconglangle A',<_Rcap(A'times A')rangle$$
Is it necessarily true that $langle A,<_Rrangleconglangle B,<_Srangle$?
The original statement talked about well-ordered sets, but that case is pretty easy, because supposing that $langle B',<_Scap(B'times B')rangle$ is not isomorphic to $langle B,<_Srangle$, the theorem of comparison between well-ordered sets assures that $B'$ with its restricted relation $<_S$ is isomorphic to an initial section of $langle B,<_Srangle$. But then, composing the unique isomorphism between $A$ and $B'$ with the restriction to $B'$ of the only isomorphism between $B$ and $A'$, we find that $A$ is isomorphic to a subset of $A$ with strict upper bounds (namely, the image of the element of $B$ that defines the initial section of $B'$ via the isomorphism between $B$ and $A'$) in the sense of $<_R$, which is absurd.
However, when the sets are not well-ordered, can we find a couple of linearly ordered sets that, although verifying the stated property, are not isomorphic to each other?
I have tried with many examples between subsets of $mathbb{R}$ and other subsets of $mathbb{R}$, but it seems that they are all isomorphic to each other.
I ran out of ideas. Are there any counterexamples to this statement? Or does this property actually characterize when two ordered structures are isomorphic? In case the second part holds, why is that the case?
Thanks in advance for your time.
P.S.: I have thought, for instance, that a closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ shouldn't be isomorphic to the whole $mathbb{R}$. How can we prove this assertion, if true?
elementary-set-theory examples-counterexamples order-theory
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I have encountered myself with the following exercise:
Let $langle A, <_Rrangle$ and $langle B, <_Srangle$ be two linearly ordered sets so that each one is isomorphic to a subset of the other, that is, there exists $A'subseteq A$ and $B'subseteq B$ such that:
$$langle A,<_Rrangleconglangle B',<_Scap(B'times B')rangleqquad&qquadlangle B,<_Srangleconglangle A',<_Rcap(A'times A')rangle$$
Is it necessarily true that $langle A,<_Rrangleconglangle B,<_Srangle$?
The original statement talked about well-ordered sets, but that case is pretty easy, because supposing that $langle B',<_Scap(B'times B')rangle$ is not isomorphic to $langle B,<_Srangle$, the theorem of comparison between well-ordered sets assures that $B'$ with its restricted relation $<_S$ is isomorphic to an initial section of $langle B,<_Srangle$. But then, composing the unique isomorphism between $A$ and $B'$ with the restriction to $B'$ of the only isomorphism between $B$ and $A'$, we find that $A$ is isomorphic to a subset of $A$ with strict upper bounds (namely, the image of the element of $B$ that defines the initial section of $B'$ via the isomorphism between $B$ and $A'$) in the sense of $<_R$, which is absurd.
However, when the sets are not well-ordered, can we find a couple of linearly ordered sets that, although verifying the stated property, are not isomorphic to each other?
I have tried with many examples between subsets of $mathbb{R}$ and other subsets of $mathbb{R}$, but it seems that they are all isomorphic to each other.
I ran out of ideas. Are there any counterexamples to this statement? Or does this property actually characterize when two ordered structures are isomorphic? In case the second part holds, why is that the case?
Thanks in advance for your time.
P.S.: I have thought, for instance, that a closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ shouldn't be isomorphic to the whole $mathbb{R}$. How can we prove this assertion, if true?
elementary-set-theory examples-counterexamples order-theory
$endgroup$
I have encountered myself with the following exercise:
Let $langle A, <_Rrangle$ and $langle B, <_Srangle$ be two linearly ordered sets so that each one is isomorphic to a subset of the other, that is, there exists $A'subseteq A$ and $B'subseteq B$ such that:
$$langle A,<_Rrangleconglangle B',<_Scap(B'times B')rangleqquad&qquadlangle B,<_Srangleconglangle A',<_Rcap(A'times A')rangle$$
Is it necessarily true that $langle A,<_Rrangleconglangle B,<_Srangle$?
The original statement talked about well-ordered sets, but that case is pretty easy, because supposing that $langle B',<_Scap(B'times B')rangle$ is not isomorphic to $langle B,<_Srangle$, the theorem of comparison between well-ordered sets assures that $B'$ with its restricted relation $<_S$ is isomorphic to an initial section of $langle B,<_Srangle$. But then, composing the unique isomorphism between $A$ and $B'$ with the restriction to $B'$ of the only isomorphism between $B$ and $A'$, we find that $A$ is isomorphic to a subset of $A$ with strict upper bounds (namely, the image of the element of $B$ that defines the initial section of $B'$ via the isomorphism between $B$ and $A'$) in the sense of $<_R$, which is absurd.
However, when the sets are not well-ordered, can we find a couple of linearly ordered sets that, although verifying the stated property, are not isomorphic to each other?
I have tried with many examples between subsets of $mathbb{R}$ and other subsets of $mathbb{R}$, but it seems that they are all isomorphic to each other.
I ran out of ideas. Are there any counterexamples to this statement? Or does this property actually characterize when two ordered structures are isomorphic? In case the second part holds, why is that the case?
Thanks in advance for your time.
P.S.: I have thought, for instance, that a closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ shouldn't be isomorphic to the whole $mathbb{R}$. How can we prove this assertion, if true?
elementary-set-theory examples-counterexamples order-theory
elementary-set-theory examples-counterexamples order-theory
edited 41 mins ago
Andrés E. Caicedo
66.3k8160252
66.3k8160252
asked 1 hour ago
AkerbeltzAkerbeltz
378216
378216
add a comment |
add a comment |
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
This should work: the real intervals $I = (-1, 1)$ and $J = [-1, 1]$ with the usual ordering are order isomorphic to subsets of one another:
$I$, being a subset of $J$, is obviously order isomorphic to itself
$J$ is order isomorphic to $I' = [-frac{1}{2}, frac{1}{2}] subset I$ by the scaling map $omega : J ni j mapsto frac{1}{2}j in I'$
However, $I$ and $J$ are not isomorphic to each other because $J$ has a least element $-1$ and a greatest element $1$ while $I$ has neither.
Indeed, order isomorphisms must preserve the existence of least and greatest elements.
For if $j_text{min}$ were the least element of $J$ and $J$ were order isomorphic to $I$ by an order isomorphism $omega$, then $omega(j_text{min})$ must be the least element of $I$. To see this, let $i in I$ be any element. Then the unique preimage $j = omega^{-1}(i) in J$ of $i$ must be greater than $j_text{min}$ by definition of $j_text{min}$ being the least element of $J$. That is, $j_text{min} leq_J j$. So as $phi$ is order preserving, this implies $omega(j_text{min}) leq_I omega(j) = i$. So, $omega(j_text{min})$ is indeed smaller than every element of $I$.
P.S.: I have thought, for instance, that a closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ shouldn't be isomorphic to the whole $mathbb{R}$. How can we prove this assertion, if true?
Using the exact same idea as before, you can show this to be true. Any closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ must have a least element; however, $mathbb{R}$ does not have a least element.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3205468%2fcounterexample-a-pair-of-linearly-ordered-sets-that-are-isomorphic-to-subsets-o%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
This should work: the real intervals $I = (-1, 1)$ and $J = [-1, 1]$ with the usual ordering are order isomorphic to subsets of one another:
$I$, being a subset of $J$, is obviously order isomorphic to itself
$J$ is order isomorphic to $I' = [-frac{1}{2}, frac{1}{2}] subset I$ by the scaling map $omega : J ni j mapsto frac{1}{2}j in I'$
However, $I$ and $J$ are not isomorphic to each other because $J$ has a least element $-1$ and a greatest element $1$ while $I$ has neither.
Indeed, order isomorphisms must preserve the existence of least and greatest elements.
For if $j_text{min}$ were the least element of $J$ and $J$ were order isomorphic to $I$ by an order isomorphism $omega$, then $omega(j_text{min})$ must be the least element of $I$. To see this, let $i in I$ be any element. Then the unique preimage $j = omega^{-1}(i) in J$ of $i$ must be greater than $j_text{min}$ by definition of $j_text{min}$ being the least element of $J$. That is, $j_text{min} leq_J j$. So as $phi$ is order preserving, this implies $omega(j_text{min}) leq_I omega(j) = i$. So, $omega(j_text{min})$ is indeed smaller than every element of $I$.
P.S.: I have thought, for instance, that a closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ shouldn't be isomorphic to the whole $mathbb{R}$. How can we prove this assertion, if true?
Using the exact same idea as before, you can show this to be true. Any closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ must have a least element; however, $mathbb{R}$ does not have a least element.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
This should work: the real intervals $I = (-1, 1)$ and $J = [-1, 1]$ with the usual ordering are order isomorphic to subsets of one another:
$I$, being a subset of $J$, is obviously order isomorphic to itself
$J$ is order isomorphic to $I' = [-frac{1}{2}, frac{1}{2}] subset I$ by the scaling map $omega : J ni j mapsto frac{1}{2}j in I'$
However, $I$ and $J$ are not isomorphic to each other because $J$ has a least element $-1$ and a greatest element $1$ while $I$ has neither.
Indeed, order isomorphisms must preserve the existence of least and greatest elements.
For if $j_text{min}$ were the least element of $J$ and $J$ were order isomorphic to $I$ by an order isomorphism $omega$, then $omega(j_text{min})$ must be the least element of $I$. To see this, let $i in I$ be any element. Then the unique preimage $j = omega^{-1}(i) in J$ of $i$ must be greater than $j_text{min}$ by definition of $j_text{min}$ being the least element of $J$. That is, $j_text{min} leq_J j$. So as $phi$ is order preserving, this implies $omega(j_text{min}) leq_I omega(j) = i$. So, $omega(j_text{min})$ is indeed smaller than every element of $I$.
P.S.: I have thought, for instance, that a closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ shouldn't be isomorphic to the whole $mathbb{R}$. How can we prove this assertion, if true?
Using the exact same idea as before, you can show this to be true. Any closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ must have a least element; however, $mathbb{R}$ does not have a least element.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
This should work: the real intervals $I = (-1, 1)$ and $J = [-1, 1]$ with the usual ordering are order isomorphic to subsets of one another:
$I$, being a subset of $J$, is obviously order isomorphic to itself
$J$ is order isomorphic to $I' = [-frac{1}{2}, frac{1}{2}] subset I$ by the scaling map $omega : J ni j mapsto frac{1}{2}j in I'$
However, $I$ and $J$ are not isomorphic to each other because $J$ has a least element $-1$ and a greatest element $1$ while $I$ has neither.
Indeed, order isomorphisms must preserve the existence of least and greatest elements.
For if $j_text{min}$ were the least element of $J$ and $J$ were order isomorphic to $I$ by an order isomorphism $omega$, then $omega(j_text{min})$ must be the least element of $I$. To see this, let $i in I$ be any element. Then the unique preimage $j = omega^{-1}(i) in J$ of $i$ must be greater than $j_text{min}$ by definition of $j_text{min}$ being the least element of $J$. That is, $j_text{min} leq_J j$. So as $phi$ is order preserving, this implies $omega(j_text{min}) leq_I omega(j) = i$. So, $omega(j_text{min})$ is indeed smaller than every element of $I$.
P.S.: I have thought, for instance, that a closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ shouldn't be isomorphic to the whole $mathbb{R}$. How can we prove this assertion, if true?
Using the exact same idea as before, you can show this to be true. Any closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ must have a least element; however, $mathbb{R}$ does not have a least element.
$endgroup$
This should work: the real intervals $I = (-1, 1)$ and $J = [-1, 1]$ with the usual ordering are order isomorphic to subsets of one another:
$I$, being a subset of $J$, is obviously order isomorphic to itself
$J$ is order isomorphic to $I' = [-frac{1}{2}, frac{1}{2}] subset I$ by the scaling map $omega : J ni j mapsto frac{1}{2}j in I'$
However, $I$ and $J$ are not isomorphic to each other because $J$ has a least element $-1$ and a greatest element $1$ while $I$ has neither.
Indeed, order isomorphisms must preserve the existence of least and greatest elements.
For if $j_text{min}$ were the least element of $J$ and $J$ were order isomorphic to $I$ by an order isomorphism $omega$, then $omega(j_text{min})$ must be the least element of $I$. To see this, let $i in I$ be any element. Then the unique preimage $j = omega^{-1}(i) in J$ of $i$ must be greater than $j_text{min}$ by definition of $j_text{min}$ being the least element of $J$. That is, $j_text{min} leq_J j$. So as $phi$ is order preserving, this implies $omega(j_text{min}) leq_I omega(j) = i$. So, $omega(j_text{min})$ is indeed smaller than every element of $I$.
P.S.: I have thought, for instance, that a closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ shouldn't be isomorphic to the whole $mathbb{R}$. How can we prove this assertion, if true?
Using the exact same idea as before, you can show this to be true. Any closed interval of $mathbb{R}$ must have a least element; however, $mathbb{R}$ does not have a least element.
edited 8 mins ago
answered 52 mins ago
ZeroXLRZeroXLR
1,965620
1,965620
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3205468%2fcounterexample-a-pair-of-linearly-ordered-sets-that-are-isomorphic-to-subsets-o%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown